SUBSCRIBER:


past masters commons

Annotation Guide:

cover
The Ordinatio of John Duns Scotus
cover
Ordinatio. Book 4. Distinctions 14 - 42.
Book Four. Distinctions 14 - 42
Sixteenth Distinction
Question One. Whether these Three, Contrition, Confession, and Satisfaction, are the Parts of Penitence

Question One. Whether these Three, Contrition, Confession, and Satisfaction, are the Parts of Penitence

1. “Now in the perfection of penitence” [Lombard, Sent. IV d.16 ch.1 n.1]

2. About this sixteenth distinction I ask first whether contrition, confession, and satisfaction are the parts of penitence.

3. That they are not:

Sin is a simple defect;     therefore a simple remedy can answer to it; penitence is such a remedy; therefore etc     .

4. Again, if there were parts to penitence, either integral or subjective parts (and I take ‘integral’ in common for the essential and quantitative parts). Not integral parts because the whole is not predicated of such a part; but to be contrite is to be penitent, and to confess is to be penitent, and to satisfy is to be penitent;     therefore etc     . Nor subjective parts, because in any subjective part the idea of the whole, without the other part, is perfectly preserved. For Socrates would be perfectly man though there were no further supposits in the human species; but in contrition without the other parts the idea of penitence is not perfectly preserved;     therefore etc     .

5. Again, if they were parts, either of penitence the virtue or of penitence the sacrament.

Not the first, because penitence the virtue is a simple form in the soul, spiritual, and consequently indivisible. In like manner, confession and satisfaction are not spiritual but certain sensible things outside the mind.

Nor the second, because every sacrament is a sensible sign, or consists in a sensible sign; contrition is not anything sensible but something spiritual in the soul;     therefore , it is not part of the sacrament.

6. Again, no part is posterior in order of nature to its whole; but satisfaction follows penitence in natural order; therefore etc     .

7. Again, fruit is not part of that of which it is the fruit (it is plain both by example, as an apple is not a part of the tree of which it is the fruit; and by reason, because fruit is the final thing that is waited for from that of which it is the fruit). But now satisfaction is the fruit of penitence [supra, d.15 nn.32-33], according to the gloss34 on Matthew 3.8 “Bring forth fruit worthy of penitence,” and according to [Ps-]Augustine, On True and False Penitence ch..14-15 nn.29-31 (and it is in the text in this distinction 16 [Lombard, Sent. IV d.16 ch.2 nn.1-5]).

8. To the contrary:

The master says in the text [Sent. IV d.16 ch.1 n.1] that these three things are required for the perfection of penitence: but several things are not required for the perfection of something unless they are parts of it;     therefore etc     .

I. To the Question

A. About the Many Ways of Taking the Term ‘To Be Penitent’

9. Here one needs to understand that, besides the way according to which ‘penitence’ is taken for the sacrament of penitence [infra n.25], ‘penitence’, or rather ‘to be penitent’, can be taken in many other ways:

For as is had from what was said in distinction 14 questions 2 and 3 [nn.86-92, 168, 187], penitence happens to have a sort of justice avenging its own proper sin; and next to that there is an elicited act proper to it, which is a certain imperative willing of a penalty, as of what avenges the fault; in third rank is an effect next to the elicited act, which effect is an act, or acts, on which follows a penalty of avenging (for the will cannot, by an act of will, command a penalty save by first commanding the cause of the penalty, because passions are not in the power of the will save by the mediation of acts); fourth and last there follows the penalty consequent to the act commanded by the elicited act of penitence itself as virtue; and the penalty is the remote effect of the elicited act.35

10. The distinction between all these is plain from the fact that they can be separated from each other:36

For the virtue can exist without the elicited act (as is plain of itself) and conversely, because (as was said) the first act conformed to right reason (of a nature to generate virtue) can be had before anything of virtue is had, because it is the cause of generation of the first degree of virtue.

11. Similarly, the elicited act, which is second, can be without the third, namely without the commanded act, because an act that is commanded does not at once follow the act of command in the will (because the will in commanding is not omnipotent), and conversely.

12. The third can be without the second, namely some act causative of a penalty can be without the act of the will commanding this act, just as someone can at once have detestation of a sin, committed by himself, from contemplation of God, though he not command such an act to be elicited as avenging the fault.

13. The third can also be without the fourth, because those acts that would be of a nature to generate the penalty are not always followed by the penalty, because of indisposition perhaps in the power itself that is receptive of the penalty, just as on the willing-against, or hatred, of sin committed sadness does not always follow, as was said before.

14. And the fourth can also be without the third, because this penalty can be without this ordered act that would be of a nature to cause the penalty, because that act, as ordered, is not the precise cause of the generation of the penalty.

Each one of these, then, can be without any other, and any two or three can be together without any other or any others.

15. To the matter at hand, about the term ‘to be penitent’, properly it is (as was said before d.14 n.61) ‘to hold a penalty’; but ‘to hold’ includes the act of the holder, namely that he hold it voluntarily, and the application of the penalty to himself, that he hold it in himself. This habit, therefore, can be called ‘penitence’, which is a certain habitual holding of the penalty, as a principle habitually inclining to inflicting a penalty on oneself voluntarily; and the elicited act of it can be called ‘actual penitence’ or ‘the to be penitent that is a certain willing inflictive of a penalty on oneself’; and the next act, commanded by the elicited act of justice, can be called ‘to be penitent’, because it is to have a penalty in oneself, at least in its cause; nor can something that is equally principally an object of will be otherwise had as in its cause; the fourth, namely, ‘to be punished with a penalty following that act’, is not properly to be penitent but rather (so to say) to be made penitent, that is, to be held by the penalty or, in more common usage, to be punished.

B. About these Ways of Taking the Term with Respect to Penitence as Virtue

16. To the issue at hand:

The three things aforesaid [sc. contrition, confession, satisfaction, n.2] are in no way parts of penitence as virtue (the way argued to the main point [nn.2-7]), because that virtue is a certain simple form in the will, as is charity and anything else other than justice.37 And the point is plain from something else, that it is permanent, just as it is permanent things that belong to virtue. But contrition and confession and satisfaction are certain things that have their being in their coming-to-be; but a permanent thing does not consist of parts that have their being in their coming-to-be. Again, the last two [sc. confession and satisfaction] are not in the will as in a subject, but are certain exterior things.

17. Likewise I say that they are not parts of penitence said in the second way [n.9], because that act too is a certain simple act, as it is an act of a simple virtue. It is plain too from something else, that the act is immediately from the will itself, as elicited by the will; but confession and satisfaction are not acts immediately elicited by the will but commanded by it.

18. Speaking, however, of penitence in the third way, namely for the proximate cause of the very punishment to be inflicted, which is an act commanded by an act of penitence as virtue, of this can those three things be parts.

19. And similarly the three penalties, which are concomitant with the three acts, can be posited as parts of the fourth part, which is ‘to be punished’. And this in the following way: commutative justice has regard universally to equality in exchange, and this is not an equality of the thing but rather an equality according to right reason. And in this way, therefore, penitence or punitive justice in itself, which is a certain commutative justice in punishment, has regard to the penalty equal to, or commensurate with, the fault, and this according to the right reason of the law according to which it is avenging justice.

20. Now that law, according to which penitence as virtue is avenging, dictates that guilt must be ordered both through a penalty intrinsic to sadness and through a double extrinsic penalty (namely of shame and bodily affliction or labor), as is gathered from the diverse Scriptures [d.14 nn.37, 163-166] that contain that law; therefore, the penalty, or the being punished, which responds to the fault, is integrated from three penalties.

21. And likewise, the proximate cause of the penalty must be what is integrated from the causes proper to these penalties.

22. Now the cause proper to interior sadness is detestation of the sin committed, or displeasure about the sin. And this includes two partial causes, namely consideration of the sin committed, and the willing-against of it, and among these the more principal cause is the willing-against; also, when posited, it necessarily posits the other, but not conversely.

23. The act, then, which is the proximate proper cause of sadness, is called contrition; the second act, which is the proximate cause of blushing or shame, is called confession, where the hidden sin is made manifest to a human being. The third cause proper to the third penalty is some laborious or penal work.

24. Just as, therefore, the perfect penalty, which corresponds to the fault according to avenging justice, has three partial penalties, which are parts of one perfect punishment, in the way in which three restitutions would be parts of one perfect restitution for him who would have suffered loss in such a way - so the three acts, on which the three penalties follow, are parts of one sufficient cause proximate in regard to a fitting penalty.

C. About these Ways of Taking the Term with Respect to Penitence as Sacrament

25. About penitence as a sacrament I say that those three are in no way parts of it because, as was said in distinction 14 [n.195], penitence as a sacrament is ‘absolution by a priest done with certain words etc.’ But no part of this is contrition, which is something spiritual in the soul; nor is it confession, because confession is not anything of the sentence itself of the priest, but an act of the guilty party accusing himself; nor is it satisfaction, but satisfaction follows the sacramental absolution.

26. However these three are required as preparatory to, or following from, the sacrament of penitence, so that it may be worthily received.

For confession is simply required, because the priest does not absolve by his sentence unless the guilty party has first accused himself in that forum [of the sacrament].

Nor even is the absolution useful unless some contrition or attrition precede in the one confessing. Now the reason for this distinction is plain from what was said above [n.9, d.14 n.62]; for it suffices that some displeasure, although unformed, precede, and then he is capable of sacramental absolution, and through it contrition comes to be.

Now satisfaction ought to follow the sacrament of penitence so that the sacrament be effective, and this effectiveness I understand to be in reality or in will - unless the judge could make assessment that the preceding other penalties were sufficient for payment of the whole penalty. Now this judgment of the priest gives absolution in such a way that, however, it still binds: it absolves from the debt of eternal penalty, but it binds for the payment of temporal penalty, unless this already be sufficiently paid. Also, this judgment either does not absolve at all, or at least not efficaciously, if the guilty party is not in himself disposed in the due way; because the sacrament is a sign of interior absolution, and the interior absolution does not accompany the sacrament unless there be a due disposition in the mind of the one who is to be interiorly absolved.

II. To the Initial Arguments

27. To the first main argument [n.3]: it does not follow that, if a sin be simple, the avenging remedy is simple; for a legislator can justly establish that many partial penalties correspond to one sin as one integral revenge.

28. To the second [n.4] I say that when penitence, taken in the third or fourth mode [n.9], is correspondent to some sin, it can be taken in two ways:

In one way for what is of a sort to be adequately correspondent to it, and in this way a single penitence and a single penalty correspond to a single fault and, if the fault has them as parts, it is disposed to them as to integral parts.

In another way, penitence can be taken (when stated in the third or fourth way) for the general idea of what it is ‘to hold a penalty’, or to be punished for a fault, even if not adequately; and thus is it a whole universal to things that are integral parts of it in the first way. This is plain in an example. For suppose someone has killed another: there can be a just law that he be punished with a bodily punishment, and that a monetary penalty be handed over to the friends of the person killed; each of these is a penalty, and a penalty for homicide. In this way can it be called a penalty universal with respect to the monetary and bodily penalty, because each of these is the penalty, and for this sin. In another way, taking the penalty for homicide to be the total and adequate penalty for the fault, neither the bodily nor the monetary punishment is that penalty but an integral part of that penalty.

29. And it is plain how, according to this, penitence is predicated of any of these three separately [contrition, confession, satisfaction], taking them for what holds of any penalty corresponding to the fault but not totally and adequately; and it is plain how, on the other side, none of them without the other makes the penitence complete - and understand this as what is adequate to the fault.

30. To the third argument [n.5], it is plain that they [the three of contrition, confession, satisfaction] are not parts of penitence as sacrament nor of penitence as virtue, nor even parts of the act of the virtue, but they are acts commanded by the virtue, which is the proximate punitive act; and it is plain that the penalties accompanying those acts are parts of the remote effect of the act of penitence. But the elicited act of penitence could in some way be said to have those parts not formally but quasi causally, to the extent the act is in some way distinct as it commands this part and that; and in this way could they be called parts of virtue as penitence, as this inclines to inflicting all of them.

31. To the fifth argument38 [n.7] I say that of penitence as virtue and of its elicited act and of its commanded act the laborious exterior act is the fruit; and in this way must the exterior work worked be understood. And I concede that that work is not part of penitence in any of the three ways stated. It is yet part of what ‘to be punished’ is, which is the fourth among the parts enumerated before [n.9]; and it is not unacceptable that the same thing is part of something prior and fruit of something posterior.39